Book Review: Victor Kattan's From Coexistence to Conquest

Arundhati Roy has called Palestine one of “imperial Britain’s
festering, blood-drenched gifts to the modern world.” Victor
Kattan’s book From Coexistence to Conquest: International Law
and the Origins of the Arab-Israeli Conflict, 1891-1949 leaves
no doubt her description is apt.
The story behind why the British would support the idea
of establishing a “national home” for one people within the
territory of another and how this novel "experiment" came to
fruition is the subject of this excellent book. The author, an
international law expert, describes the pivotal role that
international law, and the lack of its enforcement, played in the
creation of Israel and offers a general legal history of the
conflict.
What makes this book important and unique is Kattan’s use of a
wide range of newly disclosed historical sources, including
declassified legal opinions, minutes, telegrams, reports and
memoranda, in addition to traditional sources such as UN documents,
books and law journals. I will highlight a few of the book’s
salient points and revelations that may surprise some readers,
citing a narrow selection of this extensive research and legal
analysis.
Origin of the Arab-Israeli Conflict
The book begins by addressing the origins of the Arab-Israeli
conflict. In Kattan’s view, the conflict is rooted in anti-Semitism
and colonialism, the driving forces behind British support for
Zionism and ultimately the successful colonization of Palestine and
creation of Israel. Zionism, he argues, provided anti-Semites in
the British government with a pretext to stem the immigration to
Britain of Jews fleeing persecution in Eastern Europe and Russia by
diverting them to Palestine, while also supporting Britain’s
imperial aims in the Middle East.
Alien immigration was a sensitive issue in England in the
early twentieth century when anti-Semitism was common even among
the educated elite. Kattan quotes A.J. Balfour making abhorrent
statements about the “miseries created for western civilization by
the presence of [Jews]” (pp. 20-21), and arguing that their Russian
persecutors “had a case of their own” since Russians “were afraid
of them” (p. 20). No surprise that he led the passage of
legislation in 1905 restricting Jewish immigration to Britain.
Kattan argues that within this historical context, the Balfour
Declaration in which the British government stated its favorable
view of "the establishment in Palestine of a national home for the
Jewish people" should be interpreted as Balfour’s solution to the
“problem” of Jewish immigration.
If anti-Semitism provided the motive, colonialism provided the
means to effect the Zionist project. The colonization of Palestine
imitated other colonial models, except that it did not involve any
desire to "civilize" or exploit the native population. The Zionists
wanted the land with as few Arabs as possible – in Theodor Herzl’s
famous words: “we shall try to spirit the penniless population
across the border” (p. 34). Clearly, the Zionists had no regard for
the possibility that Palestinians had a say in their destiny, or
that they had a right to live on their land at all. Kattan spends
much of the book analyzing exactly how far the British went in
supporting this vision.
A Palestinian Right to Self-determination?
In 1937, Winston Churchill said of the Palestinians: “I do not
agree that the dog in a manger has the final right to the manger,
even though he may have lain there a very long time.” Putting aside
the statement’s appalling racism, was he right that Palestinians
were not entitled to independence and statehood in Palestine? After
a comprehensive legal analysis, Kattan concludes that prevailing
international law and British colonial policy provided ample
support for a Palestinian right to self-determination.
The Balfour Declaration of 1917, the British Mandate of
Palestine of 1922, and the UN Partition Plan of 1947, which
Zionists view as the legal basis for the legitimacy of the Jewish
state, in Kattan’s view also contained language that supported,
implied and assumed a Palestinian right to self-determination.
Although self-determination was not “an independent legal right”
(p. 120) for all peoples until decolonization in the 1960s, Kattan
explains that by the time the League of Nations was established in
1919, the Great Powers did apply that right to colonized peoples
albeit through an “evolutionary process” via the mandate system.
That system was established in the League of Nations Covenant,
which referred to “certain communities formerly belonging to the
Turkish Empire [which would include the Arabs of Palestine]
which deserved “provisional recognition” as independent
states” (p. 129). The mandate system was intended to assist
colonized peoples to advance to a stage of development at which
they could govern themselves. Palestine’s “A-Class” mandate status
meant that it was considered sufficiently advanced to merit
“provisional recognition” of independence.
The contradiction between Zionism and the above principles is
obvious, however. Not only were the indigenous Palestinians
outraged by the British Mandate, with its provision for a "Jewish
national home" in their homeland, the policy was controversial
among British officials as well. Balfour’s successor Lord Curzon
remarked sardonically: “it is quite clear that this mandate has
been drawn up by someone reeling under the fumes of Zionism” (p.
124). He spent much of his tenure as Foreign Secretary attempting
to dilute the provisions for the "Jewish national home." For
example, Kattan reveals minutes and correspondence indicating the
word "claim" in relation to Zionists’ rights in Palestine was
omitted from the Mandate re-draft on the ground that Britain
intended merely to “make room” for a Jewish national home, not to
reconstitute Palestine as a Jewish state (p. 124).
Kattan also argues that the terms of the Mandate envisaged
“one people for the purpose of self-determination…with Jewish
self-determination envisaged only within the context of the
self-determination of Palestine as a whole” (p. 128). In his view,
the Mandate’s failure to mention Arabs in Palestine by name
(instead of indirectly as “non-Jewish inhabitants”) did not negate
their rights; and the reason the Mandate contained so many
provisions to establish the Jewish national home was that the vast
majority of Jews in the early 1920s were not physically present in
Palestine while the Arabs already had centuries of continuous
occupation there.
In support of this argument, Kattan cites documents such as
the 1939 White Paper published by the British government, which
stated that its objective in Palestine was the establishment of “an
independent state in which two peoples, Arabs and Jews, share
authority in government in such a way that the essential interests
of each are shared” (p. 122); and a 1922 White Paper drafted by
Winston Churchill which declared that “the status of all citizens
of Palestine in the eyes of the law shall be Palestinian and it has
never been intended that they, or any section of them,
should possess any other juridical status” (p. 128).
Clearly, though, whatever right to self-governance had been
recognized for Palestinians, that right was seriously compromised
by the Balfour Declaration. But Kattan points out that even that
document contained clauses safeguarding the civil and religious
rights of non-Jewish communities in Palestine, and referred to a
Jewish home within Palestine, not a Jewish state. While it
has been argued that absence of the word "political" negated
Palestinian self-determination rights, Kattan cites sources that
suggest otherwise, such as Mandate drafting discussions in which
Lord Curzon noted that under British law, civil rights included
political rights. Much of the private correspondence and memoranda
Kattan reveals indicate that when British officials communicated
among themselves, a Palestinian right to self-determination
was assumed and even explicitly recognized. Lord Balfour himself,
chief architect of the "national home policy,” admitted in private
correspondence with Lord Curzon that the Zionists’ “position was
weak” because it “declined to accept the principle of
self-determination” of Palestine’s “present inhabitants,” and
that Zionism was a “flagrant” contradiction of “the letter of the
[League of Nations] Covenant” (p. 123).
There is a difficulty, however, with Kattan’s use of opinions
expressed in private to interpret legal documents and public
statements in that he does not always take into account that the
colonial powers often engaged in double-speak, claiming to protect
those they were simultaneously oppressing. The mere fact that
British officials privately spoke of certain Palestinian rights
does not necessarily mean they intended to protect those rights in
legally binding documents or statements of official policy that
were in all likelihood deliberately vague and ambiguous. Should the
back-tracking in the White Papers and redraft of the Mandate, for
instance, be taken at face value, or was it really calculated
political maneuvering designed to quell Arab anger? Perhaps more
skepticism is called for in drawing a link between British
officials’ private knowledge and public actions.
Whatever the British intended regarding the level of
compromise of Palestinian rights, one can conclude that although
colonialism was still "legal" during this period, international law
had advanced to a stage where rights of indigenous peoples,
including the right to self-determination, were recognized and to
be protected. The establishment of a national home, not to mention
a state, for a people with no connection to a territory other than
a claim of exile nineteen hundred years earlier, in a land where
they were vastly outnumbered by a people with centuries of
continuous residence was as much an anomaly then as it would be
today.
Misconceptions About Israel’s Creation
Israelis today generally point to the UN Partition Plan as the
basis for legitimacy of the Jewish state. Kattan makes a strong
case that Israel could not legally have achieved statehood
via the UN Partition Plan because, on its own, the resolution (UN
General Assembly Resolution 181) was non-binding, and it was not
implemented by the UN Security Council or the British, as would
have been required for it to become binding. His argument is based
on the fact that the UN Charter generally only grants the General
Assembly the authority to make non-binding resolutions; the
authorization of Resolution 181 by Article 10, which only
authorizes non-binding resolutions; the language of the resolution
which is explicit in its being a recommendation; and the opinion of
the UN Secretariat at the time that the Resolution effecting
partition had ‘no obligatory character whatsoever’ although the
Security Council could choose to enforce the plan (p.155). Thus, it
was up to the UN Security Council or the British as the mandatory
power to enforce the plan, and both declined to do so.
Legal technicalities about enforcement aside, in practical
effect the partition resolution gave the Zionists the legitimacy
they needed to establish the Jewish state. Lack of enforcement
would have defeated their claim to legitimacy, however, if
events at the UN had not been pre-empted by the outbreak of
hostilities on the ground. Kattan recounts a sequence of legal
events just prior to the war between the Zionist militias and the
Arab armies that may surprise some readers.
When it came time to enforce the partition plan, it finally
dawned on the US that the plan was practically unenforceable, of
questionable legality and clearly unjust. They could not secure the
necessary votes in the Security Council for enforcement and the
British refused to do so as well. Arab representatives accused the
US of undue influence on weaker states to vote in favor of
partition, and argued convincingly that their right to
self-determination was disregarded. The inequity of the partition
was obvious. Jews were granted fifty-seven percent of the land
although they constituted only thirty-three percent of the
population and Zionist organizations controlled less than seven
percent of the country's territory, and they were allotted
eight-four percent of the agricultural land, while agriculture was
the historic core of the economy in Palestine and citrus fruit the
largest export. Jews were also given most of the Naqab (Negev)
though they made up less than one percent of its population.
Kattan explains that, faced with the prospect of implementing
an unworkable partition plan by force, the U.S. did an about-face
and proposed a UN trusteeship which provided, among other things,
that there would be one state of Palestine, that Arabs and Jews
would agree on their form of government by referendum, and that
future immigration would not be based on race or religion. In
short, the trusteeship would have protected the right to
self-determination of both peoples. As it turned out, the
trusteeship was never voted on as war had begun and the Zionists
ultimately imposed their own version of partition by force, going
well beyond the recommendations of the partition plan, driving
hundreds of thousands of Palestinians from their homes through
deliberate and carefully planned military operations. Ultimately,
partition was effected through the 1949 armistice agreements with
the surrounding Arab states.
On 14 May 1948, Israel unilaterally declared its independence.
Kattan reveals that the U.S. delegation to the UN, working to
effect an equitable solution to the conflict, was stunned by
Truman’s immediate recognition of the Israeli state. They had
received no warning. Apparently, U.S. diplomats (according to
declassified top secret memoranda) did not view the idea of a
Jewish state favorably, and did not believe the Balfour Declaration
required that they support one.
As the UN had not been given the opportunity to vote on the
trusteeship and implement a different vision, the partition
resolution has remained in effect, providing Zionists with a
credible argument that it established their state. However, despite
what Zionists and their representatives assert today, Kattan
reveals that Israel could not, as a legal matter, have been
established by the UN Partition Plan, and was in reality
established by conquest.
Israel's “Exceptional” Nature
In one of Lord Balfour’s rhapsodies on Zionism’s blissful
promise, he states: “I cannot help thinking that this experiment …
is a great experiment, because nothing like it has ever been tried
in the world, and because it is entirely novel” (p. 251). In
Balfour’s mind, Zionism and Israel were “absolutely exceptional” –
as Kattan puts it, “It was special. It was sui generis” (p.
251).
Unfortunately, this special status has also been granted to
Israel by the UN, the body with the most significant mechanisms to
enforce international law. The UN has accorded Israel virtual
impunity since its establishment (and arguably in the manner of its
establishment during the 1948 war, also addressed in this book).
Israeli leaders illegally resisted the return of the refugees
following the 1948 war and the U.S., bowing to the antecedents of
the political forces it caters to today, did not use its power to
enforce a condition on Israel’s entry to the UN which required its
compliance with international law on the question of refugees. The
Holocaust, and the refusal of other nations to accept displaced
European Jews undoubtedly played a part in this leniency; yet this
does not excuse the failure of the UN to enforce international law
vis-à-vis Israel. Even when the UN has attempted to discipline the
Jewish state, through annual affirmations of the refugees’ right of
return, and UN Security Council Resolution 242 ordering withdrawal
from the occupied Palestinian territory, Israel simply ignores the
law without consequence.
Over six decades of legal impunity, the catalog of Israeli
brutality and human rights violations has become vast. It includes:
torture, illegal detention, assassination; assaults against
civilians with missiles, helicopters, and jet fighters; annexation
of territory; transfer of civilians for purpose of imprisonment;
mass killing as in Gaza, Qana, Jenin, Sabra and Shatila; denial of
rights to free passage and unimpeded civilian movement, education,
and medical aid; use of civilians as human shields; humiliation;
house demolitions on a mass scale; destruction of agricultural
land; expropriation of water; illegal settlements; economic
pauperization; attacks on hospitals, medical workers, and
ambulances; and the killing of UN personnel, all carried on with UN
acquiescence. Even when a UN fact-finding commission finally had
the temerity to report evidence of war crimes by Israeli soldiers
in the Goldstone Report covering events in Gaza earlier this year,
accountability is a remote prospect.
What has Israel gained by this impunity? Territory that can
only be retained through a costly and brutal military occupation.
Increasingly, its officials risk arrest when they travel abroad.
Comparisons with apartheid South Africa are ubiquitous. In fact,
while some might argue Israeli impunity proves the irrelevance of
international law, one could view it as proof of the
indispensability of international law in that Israel has never
known peace. Given consistent Arab opposition to Zionism since the
nineteenth century, most likely it never will – that is, as a
nation led by a Zionist regime.
As Kattan concludes “in the end it is unlikely that a lasting
peace would subsist unless it is based on equity, justice and
principles of international law, which have been sidelined
throughout the course of the Arab-Israeli conflict to the detriment
of all concerned” (p. 261).